FALSACIONISMO KARL POPPER PDF

XXVI , no. DOI: Abstract: The Schumpeterian and neo-schumpeterian theories represent pillars on which the subject of innovation developed and gained expression. Moreover, innovation is an independent area both in national and international congresses. The objective of this essay is to investigate - from two criteria of delimitation Popper and Lakatos - the scientificity of innovation theory. Innovation is analyzed from three macro themes: i the neoclassical current of economic theory; ii the introduction of innovation theory and reviews of the more recent Schumpeter manuscripts; iii the contributions brought by the neo-chumpeterian innovation current.

Author:Tygorisar Gugar
Country:Kenya
Language:English (Spanish)
Genre:Photos
Published (Last):7 January 2017
Pages:262
PDF File Size:3.3 Mb
ePub File Size:5.66 Mb
ISBN:936-3-41624-334-9
Downloads:78046
Price:Free* [*Free Regsitration Required]
Uploader:Mooguzragore



In a world where scientific theories often sound bizarre and counter to everyday intuition, and where a wide variety of nonsense aspires to be recognized as "scientific," it's important to be able to separate science from non-science—what philosophers call "the demarcation problem. It's a well-meaning idea, but far from the complete story. Popper was concerned with theories such as Freudian psychoanalysis and Marxist economics, which he considered non-scientific.

No matter what actually happens to people or societies, Popper claimed, theories like these will always be able to tell a story in which the data are compatible with the theoretical framework. He contrasted this with Einstein's relativity, which made specific quantitative predictions ahead of time. One prediction of general relativity was that the universe should be expanding or contracting, leading Einstein to modify the theory because he thought the universe was actually static.

So even in this example the falsifiability criterion is not as unambiguous as it seems. Modern physics stretches into realms far removed from everyday experience, and sometimes the connection to experiment becomes tenuous at best. String theory and other approaches to quantum gravity involve phenomena that are likely to manifest themselves only at energies enormously higher than anything we have access to here on Earth.

The cosmological multiverse and the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics posit other realms that are impossible for us to access directly.

Some scientists, leaning on Popper, have suggested that these theories are non-scientific because they are not falsifiable. The truth is the opposite. Whether or not we can observe them directly, the entities involved in these theories are either real or they are not. Refusing to contemplate their possible existence on the grounds of some a priori principle, even though they might play a crucial role in how the world works, is as non-scientific as it gets. The falsifiability criterion gestures toward something true and important about science, but it is a blunt instrument in a situation that calls for subtlety and precision.

It is better to emphasize two more central features of good scientific theories: they are definite , and they are empirical. By "definite" we simply mean that they say something clear and unambiguous about how reality functions. String theory says that, in certain regions of parameter space, ordinary particles behave as loops or segments of one-dimensional strings. The relevant parameter space might be inaccessible to us, but it is part of the theory that cannot be avoided.

In the cosmological multiverse, regions unlike our own are unambiguously there, even if we can't reach them. This is what distinguishes these theories from the approaches Popper was trying to classify as non-scientific. Popper himself understood that theories should be falsifiable "in principle," but that modifier is often forgotten in contemporary discussions.

It's the "empirical" criterion that requires some care. At face value it might be mistaken for "makes falsifiable predictions. A scientific theory is ultimately judged by its ability to account for the data—but the steps along the way to that accounting can be quite indirect. Consider the multiverse. It is often invoked as a potential solution to some of the fine-tuning problems of contemporary cosmology.

For example, we believe there is a small but nonzero vacuum energy inherent in empty space itself. This is the leading theory to explain the observed acceleration of the universe, for which the Nobel Prize was awarded. The problem for theorists is not that vacuum energy is hard to explain; it's that the predicted value is enormously larger than what we observe. If the universe we see around us is the only one there is, the vacuum energy is a unique constant of nature, and we are faced with the problem of explaining it.

If, on the other hand, we live in a multiverse, the vacuum energy could be completely different in different regions, and an explanation suggests itself immediately: in regions where the vacuum energy is much larger, conditions are inhospitable to the existence of life. There is therefore a selection effect, and we should predict a small value of the vacuum energy. Indeed, using this precise reasoning, Steven Weinberg did predict the value of the vacuum energy, long before the acceleration of the universe was discovered.

We can't as far as we know observe other parts of the multiverse directly. But their existence has a dramatic effect on how we account for the data in the part of the multiverse we do observe. It's in that sense that the success or failure of the idea is ultimately empirical: its virtue is not that it's a neat idea or fulfills some nebulous principle of reasoning, it's that it helps us account for the data.

Even if we will never visit those other universes. Science is not merely armchair theorizing; it's about explaining the world we see, developing models that fit the data. But fitting models to data is a complex and multifaceted process, involving a give-and-take between theory and experiment, as well as the gradual development of theoretical understanding in its own right.

In complicated situations, fortune-cookie-sized mottos like "theories should be falsifiable" are no substitute for careful thinking about how science works. Fortunately, science marches on, largely heedless of amateur philosophizing. If string theory and multiverse theories help us understand the world, they will grow in acceptance.

If they prove ultimately too nebulous, or better theories come along, they will be discarded. The process might be messy, but nature is the ultimate guide. Skip to main content. All Rights Reserved. In the News [ 60 ]. Sean Carroll. Return to Table of Contents.

LALITA MADHAVA PDF

David Miller

If you do not have the Acrobat Reader installed, you may download it here. Using Knowledge. Does Valid Reasoning Matter? Selected Publications all rights in all papers reproduced here belong to the author. Dordrecht: D Reidel Publishing Co London: Fontana, Princeton: Princeton University Press

BANANA PANCAKES CHORDS UKULELE PDF

What is good science?

Become a Friend of Aeon to save articles and enjoy other exclusive benefits. Aeon email newsletters are issued by the not-for-profit, registered charity Aeon Media Group Ltd Australian Business Number 80 This Email Newsletter Privacy Statement pertains to the personally identifying information you voluntarily submit in the form of your email address to receive our email newsletters. More generally, when visiting the Aeon site you should refer to our site Privacy Policy here. This Email Newsletter Privacy Statement may change from time to time and was last revised 18 May, We are committed to ensuring that your information is secure.

Related Articles